430 lines
26 KiB
Markdown
430 lines
26 KiB
Markdown
|
# THE CRIMINAL INTENT
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
It is a maxim of the common law that there can be no crime without a
|
|||
|
criminal intent. And it is a perfectly clear principle, although one
|
|||
|
which judges have in a great measure overthrown in practice, that
|
|||
|
_jurors_ are to judge of the moral intent of an accused person, and hold
|
|||
|
him guiltless, whatever his act, unless they find him to have acted with
|
|||
|
a criminal intent; that is, with a design to do what he knew to be
|
|||
|
criminal.
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
This principle is clear, because the question for a jury to determine
|
|||
|
is, whether the accused be _guilty_, or _not guilty_. _Guilt_ is a
|
|||
|
personal quality of the actor,—not _necessarily_ involved in the act,
|
|||
|
but depending also upon the intent or motive with which the act was
|
|||
|
done. Consequently, the jury must find that he acted from a criminal
|
|||
|
motive, before they can declare him _guilty_.
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
There is no moral justice in, nor any political necessity for, punishing
|
|||
|
a man for any act whatever that he may have committed, if he have done
|
|||
|
it without any criminal intent. There can be no _moral justice_ in
|
|||
|
punishing for such an act, because, there having been no _criminal
|
|||
|
motive_, there can have been no other motive which justice can take
|
|||
|
cognizance of, as demanding or justifying punishment. There can be no
|
|||
|
_political necessity_ for punishing, to warn against similar acts in
|
|||
|
future, because, if one man have injured another, however
|
|||
|
unintentionally, he is liable, and justly liable, to a _civil_ suit for
|
|||
|
damages; and in this suit he will be compelled to make compensation for
|
|||
|
the injury, notwithstanding his innocence of any intention to injure. He
|
|||
|
must bear the consequences of his own act, instead of throwing them upon
|
|||
|
another, however innocent he may have been of any intention to do
|
|||
|
wrong. And the damages he will have to pay will be a sufficient warning
|
|||
|
to him not to do the like act again.
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
If it be alleged that there are crimes against the public, (as treason,
|
|||
|
for example, or any other resistance to government,) for which private
|
|||
|
persons can recover no damages, and that there is a political necessity
|
|||
|
for punishing for such offences, even though the party acted
|
|||
|
conscientiously, the answer is,—the government must bear with all
|
|||
|
resistance that is not so clearly wrong as to give evidence of criminal
|
|||
|
intent. In other words, the government, in all its acts, must keep
|
|||
|
itself so _clearly_ within the limits of justice, as that twelve men,
|
|||
|
taken at random, will all agree that it is in the right, or it must
|
|||
|
incur the risk of resistance, without any power to punish it. This is
|
|||
|
the mode in which the trial by jury operates to prevent the government
|
|||
|
from falling into the hands of a party, or a faction, and to keep it
|
|||
|
within such limits as _all_, or substantially _all_, the people are
|
|||
|
agreed that it may occupy.
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
This necessity for a criminal intent, to justify conviction, is proved
|
|||
|
by the issue which the jury are to try, and the verdict they are to
|
|||
|
pronounce. The “issue” they are to try is, “_guilty_” or “_not guilty_.”
|
|||
|
And those are the terms they are required to use in rendering their
|
|||
|
verdicts. But it is a plain falsehood to say that a man is “_guilty_,”
|
|||
|
unless he have done an act which he knew to be criminal.
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
This necessity for a criminal intent—in other words, for _guilt_—as a
|
|||
|
preliminary to conviction, makes it impossible that a man can be
|
|||
|
rightfully convicted for an act that is intrinsically innocent, though
|
|||
|
forbidden by the government; because guilt is an intrinsic quality of
|
|||
|
actions and motives, and not one that can be imparted to them by
|
|||
|
arbitrary legislation. All the efforts of the government, therefore, to
|
|||
|
“_make offences by statute_,” out of acts that are not criminal by
|
|||
|
nature, must necessarily be ineffectual, unless a jury will declare a
|
|||
|
man “_guilty_” for an act that is really innocent.
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
The corruption of judges, in their attempts to uphold the arbitrary
|
|||
|
authority of the government, by procuring the conviction of individuals
|
|||
|
for acts innocent in themselves, and forbidden only by some tyrannical
|
|||
|
statute, and the commission of which therefore indicates no criminal
|
|||
|
intent, is very apparent.
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
To accomplish this object, they have in modern times held it to be
|
|||
|
unnecessary that indictments should charge, as by the common law they
|
|||
|
were required to do, that an act was done “_wickedly_,” “_feloniously_,”
|
|||
|
“_with malice aforethought_,” or in any other manner that implied a
|
|||
|
criminal intent, without which there can be no criminality; but that it
|
|||
|
is sufficient to charge simply that it was done “_contrary to the form
|
|||
|
of the statute in such case made and provided_.” This form of indictment
|
|||
|
proceeds plainly upon the assumption that the government is absolute,
|
|||
|
and that it has authority to prohibit any act it pleases, however
|
|||
|
innocent in its nature the act may be. Judges have been driven to the
|
|||
|
alternative of either sanctioning this new form of indictment, (which
|
|||
|
they never had any constitutional right to sanction,) or of seeing the
|
|||
|
authority of many of the statutes of the government fall to the ground;
|
|||
|
because the acts forbidden by the statutes were so plainly innocent in
|
|||
|
their nature, that even the government itself had not the face to allege
|
|||
|
that the commission of them implied or indicated any criminal intent.
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
To get rid of the necessity of showing a criminal intent, and thereby
|
|||
|
further to enslave the people, by reducing them to the necessity of a
|
|||
|
blind, unreasoning submission to the arbitrary will of the government,
|
|||
|
and of a surrender of all right, on their own part, to judge what are
|
|||
|
their constitutional and natural rights and liberties, courts have
|
|||
|
invented another idea, which they have incorporated among the pretended
|
|||
|
_maxims_, upon which they act in criminal trials, viz., that “_ignorance
|
|||
|
of the law excuses no one_.” As if it were in the nature of things
|
|||
|
possible that there could be an excuse more absolute and complete. What
|
|||
|
else than ignorance of the law is it that excuses persons under the
|
|||
|
years of discretion, and men of imbecile minds? What else than ignorance
|
|||
|
of the law is it that excuses judges themselves for all their erroneous
|
|||
|
decisions? Nothing. They are every day committing errors, which would be
|
|||
|
crimes, but for their ignorance of the law. And yet these same judges,
|
|||
|
who claim to be _learned_ in the law, and who yet could not hold their
|
|||
|
offices for a day, but for the allowance which the law makes for their
|
|||
|
ignorance, are continually asserting it to be a “maxim” that “ignorance
|
|||
|
of the law excuses no one;” (by which, of course, they really mean that
|
|||
|
it excuses no one but themselves; and especially that it excuses no
|
|||
|
_unlearned_ man, who comes before them charged with crime.)
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
This preposterous doctrine, that “ignorance of the law excuses no one,”
|
|||
|
is asserted by courts because it is an indispensable one to the
|
|||
|
maintenance of absolute power in the government. It is indispensable for
|
|||
|
this purpose, because, if it be once admitted that the people _have_ any
|
|||
|
rights and liberties which the government cannot lawfully take from
|
|||
|
them, then the question arises in regard to every statute of the
|
|||
|
government, whether it be law, or not; that is, whether it infringe, or
|
|||
|
not, the rights and liberties of the people. Of this question every man
|
|||
|
must of course judge according to the light in his own mind. And no man
|
|||
|
can be convicted unless the jury find, not only that the statute is
|
|||
|
_law_,—that it does _not_ infringe the rights and liberties of the
|
|||
|
people,—but also that it was so clearly law, so clearly consistent with
|
|||
|
the rights and liberties of the people, as that the individual himself,
|
|||
|
who transgressed it, _knew it to be so_, and therefore had no moral
|
|||
|
excuse for transgressing it. Governments see that if ignorance of the
|
|||
|
law were allowed to excuse a man for any act whatever, it must excuse
|
|||
|
him for transgressing all statutes whatsoever, which he himself thinks
|
|||
|
inconsistent with his rights and liberties. But such a doctrine would of
|
|||
|
course be inconsistent with the maintenance of arbitrary power by the
|
|||
|
government; and hence governments will not allow the plea, although they
|
|||
|
will not confess their true reasons for disallowing it.
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
The only reasons, (if they deserve the name of reasons), that I ever
|
|||
|
knew given for the doctrine that ignorance of the law excuses no one,
|
|||
|
are these:
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
> 1. “The reason for the maxim is that of necessity. It prevails, ‘not
|
|||
|
> that all men know the law, but because it is an excuse which every
|
|||
|
> man will make, and no man can tell how to confute him.’—_Selden_,
|
|||
|
> (as quoted in the 2d edition of _Starkie on Slander_, Prelim. Disc.,
|
|||
|
> p. 140, note.)”—_Law Magazine_, (_London_,) vol. 27, p. 97.
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
This reason impliedly admits that ignorance of the law is,
|
|||
|
_intrinsically_, an ample and sufficient excuse for a crime; and that
|
|||
|
the excuse ought to be allowed, if the fact of ignorance could but be
|
|||
|
ascertained. But it asserts that this fact is incapable of being
|
|||
|
ascertained, and that therefore there is a necessity for punishing the
|
|||
|
ignorant and the knowing—that is, the innocent and the guilty—without
|
|||
|
discrimination.
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
This reason is worthy of the doctrine it is used to uphold; as if a plea
|
|||
|
of ignorance, any more than any other plea, must necessarily be believed
|
|||
|
simply because it is urged; and as if it were not a common and every-day
|
|||
|
practice of courts and juries, in both civil and criminal cases, to
|
|||
|
determine the mental capacity of individuals; as, for example, to
|
|||
|
determine whether they are of sufficient mental capacity to make
|
|||
|
reasonable contracts; whether they are lunatic; whether they are
|
|||
|
_compotes mentis_, “of sound mind and memory,” &c. &c. And there is
|
|||
|
obviously no more difficulty in a jury’s determining whether an accused
|
|||
|
person knew the law in a criminal case, than there is in determining any
|
|||
|
of these other questions that are continually determined in regard to a
|
|||
|
man’s mental capacity. For the question to be settled by the jury is not
|
|||
|
whether the accused person knew the particular _penalty_ attached to his
|
|||
|
act, (for at common law no one knew what penalty a _jury_ would attach
|
|||
|
to an offence,) but whether he knew that his act was _intrinsically
|
|||
|
criminal_. If it were _intrinsically criminal_, it was criminal at
|
|||
|
common law. If it was not intrinsically criminal, it was not criminal at
|
|||
|
common law. (At least, such was the general principle of the common law.
|
|||
|
There may have been exceptions in practice, owing to the fact that the
|
|||
|
opinions of men, as to what was intrinsically criminal, may not have
|
|||
|
been in all cases correct.)
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
A jury, then, in judging whether an accused person knew his act to be
|
|||
|
illegal, were bound first to use their own judgments, as to whether the
|
|||
|
act were _intrinsically_ criminal. If their own judgments told them the
|
|||
|
act was _intrinsically_ and _clearly_ criminal, they would naturally and
|
|||
|
reasonably infer that the accused also understood that it was
|
|||
|
intrinsically criminal, (and consequently illegal,) unless it should
|
|||
|
appear that he was either below themselves in the scale of intellect, or
|
|||
|
had had less opportunities of knowing what acts were criminal. In
|
|||
|
short, they would judge, from any and every means they might have of
|
|||
|
judging; and if they had any reasonable doubt that he knew his act to be
|
|||
|
criminal in itself, they would be bound to acquit him.
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
The second reason that has been offered for the doctrine that ignorance
|
|||
|
of the law excuses no one, is this:
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
> “Ignorance of the municipal law of the kingdom, or of the penalty
|
|||
|
> thereby inflicted on offenders, doth not excuse any that is of the
|
|||
|
> age of discretion and compos mentis, from the penalty of the breach
|
|||
|
> of it; because every person, of the age of discretion and compos
|
|||
|
> mentis, _is bound to know the law_, and presumed to do so.
|
|||
|
> _Ignorantia eorum, quæ quis scire tenetur non excusat_.” (Ignorance
|
|||
|
> of those things which every one is bound to know, does not
|
|||
|
> excuse.)—_1 Hale’s Pleas of the Crown_, 42. _Doctor and Student,
|
|||
|
> Dialog. 2_, ch. 46. _Law Magazine_, (_London_,) vol. 27, p. 97.
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
The sum of this reason is, that ignorance of the law excuses no one,
|
|||
|
(who is of the age of discretion and is compos mentis,) because every
|
|||
|
such person “_is bound to know the law_.” But this is giving no reason
|
|||
|
at all for the doctrine, since saying that a man “is bound to know the
|
|||
|
law,” is only saying, _in another form_, that “ignorance of the law does
|
|||
|
not excuse him.” There is no difference at all in the two ideas. To say,
|
|||
|
therefore, that “ignorance of the law excuses no one, _because_ every
|
|||
|
one is bound to know the law,” is only equivalent to saying that
|
|||
|
“ignorance of the law excuses no one, _because_ ignorance of the law
|
|||
|
excuses no one.” It is merely reässerting the doctrine, without giving
|
|||
|
any reason at all.
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
And yet these reasons, which are really no reasons at all, are the only
|
|||
|
ones, so far as I know, that have ever been offered for this absurd and
|
|||
|
brutal doctrine.
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
The idea suggested, that “the age of discretion” determines the guilt of
|
|||
|
a person,—that there is a particular age, prior to which _all_ persons
|
|||
|
alike should be held incapable of knowing _any_ crime, and subsequent to
|
|||
|
which _all_ persons alike should be held capable of knowing _all_
|
|||
|
crimes,—is another of this most ridiculous nest of ideas. All mankind
|
|||
|
acquire their knowledge of crimes, as they do of other things,
|
|||
|
_gradually_. Some they learn at an early age; others not till a later
|
|||
|
one. One individual acquires a knowledge of crimes, as he does of
|
|||
|
arithmetic, at an earlier age than others do. And to apply the same
|
|||
|
presumption to all, on the ground of age alone, is not only gross
|
|||
|
injustice, but gross folly. A universal presumption might, with nearly
|
|||
|
or quite as much reason, be founded upon weight, or height, as upon
|
|||
|
age.[^103]
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
This doctrine, that “ignorance of the law excuses no one,” is constantly
|
|||
|
repeated in the form that “every one is bound to know the law.” The
|
|||
|
doctrine is true in civil matters, especially in contracts, so far as
|
|||
|
this: that no man, who has the _ordinary_ capacity to make reasonable
|
|||
|
contracts, can escape the consequences of his own agreement, on the
|
|||
|
ground that he did not know the law applicable to it. When a man makes a
|
|||
|
contract, he gives the other party rights; and he must of necessity
|
|||
|
judge for himself, and take his own risk, as to what those rights
|
|||
|
are,—otherwise the contract would not be binding, and men could not
|
|||
|
make contracts that would convey rights to each other. Besides, the
|
|||
|
capacity to make reasonable contracts, _implies and includes_ a
|
|||
|
capacity to form a reasonable judgment as to the law applicable to them.
|
|||
|
But in _criminal_ matters, where the question is one of punishment, or
|
|||
|
not; where no second party has acquired any right to have the crime
|
|||
|
punished, unless it were committed with criminal intent, (but only to
|
|||
|
have it compensated for by damages in a civil suit;) and when the
|
|||
|
criminal intent is the only moral justification for the punishment, the
|
|||
|
principle does not apply, and a man is bound to know the law _only as
|
|||
|
well as he reasonably may_. The criminal law requires neither
|
|||
|
impossibilities nor extraordinaries of any one. It requires only
|
|||
|
thoughtfulness and a good conscience. It requires only that a man fairly
|
|||
|
and properly use the judgment he possesses, and the means he has of
|
|||
|
learning his duty. It requires of him only the same care to know his
|
|||
|
duty in regard to the law, that he is morally bound to use in other
|
|||
|
matters of equal importance. _And this care it does require of him._ Any
|
|||
|
ignorance of the law, therefore, that is unnecessary, or that arises
|
|||
|
from indifference or disregard of one’s duty, is no excuse. An accused
|
|||
|
person, therefore, may be rightfully held responsible for such a
|
|||
|
knowledge of the law as is common to men in general, having no greater
|
|||
|
natural capacities than himself, and no greater opportunities for
|
|||
|
learning the law. And he can rightfully be held to no greater knowledge
|
|||
|
of the law than this. To hold him responsible for a greater knowledge of
|
|||
|
the law than is common to mankind, when other things are equal, would be
|
|||
|
gross injustice and cruelty. The mass of mankind can give but little of
|
|||
|
their attention to acquiring a knowledge of the law. Their other duties
|
|||
|
in life forbid it. Of course, they cannot investigate abstruse or
|
|||
|
difficult questions. All that can rightfully be required of each of
|
|||
|
them, then, is that he exercise such a candid and conscientious judgment
|
|||
|
as it is common for mankind generally to exercise in such matters. If he
|
|||
|
have done this, it would be monstrous to punish him criminally for his
|
|||
|
errors; errors not of conscience, but only of judgment. It would also be
|
|||
|
contrary to the first principles of a free government (that is, a
|
|||
|
government formed by voluntary association) to punish men in such cases,
|
|||
|
because it would be absurd to suppose that any man would voluntarily
|
|||
|
assist to establish or support a government that would punish himself
|
|||
|
for acts which he himself did not know to be crimes. But a man may
|
|||
|
reasonably unite with his fellow-men to maintain a government to punish
|
|||
|
those acts which he himself considers criminal, and may reasonably
|
|||
|
acquiesce in his own liability to be punished for such acts. As those
|
|||
|
are the only grounds on which any one can be supposed to render any
|
|||
|
voluntary support to a government, it follows that a government formed
|
|||
|
by voluntary association, and of course having no powers except such as
|
|||
|
_all_ the associates have consented that it may have, can have no power
|
|||
|
to punish a man for acts which he did not himself know to be criminal.
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
The safety of society, which is the only object of the criminal law,
|
|||
|
requires only that those acts _which are understood by mankind at large
|
|||
|
to be intrinsically criminal_, should be punished as crimes. The
|
|||
|
remaining few (if there are any) may safely be left to go unpunished.
|
|||
|
Nor does the safety of society require that any individuals, other than
|
|||
|
those who have sufficient mental capacity to understand that their acts
|
|||
|
are criminal, should be criminally punished. All others may safely be
|
|||
|
left to their liability, under the _civil_ law, to compensate for their
|
|||
|
unintentional wrongs.
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
The only real object of this absurd and atrocious doctrine, that
|
|||
|
“ignorance of the law (that is, of crime) excuses no one,” and that
|
|||
|
“every one is bound to know the _criminal_ law,” (that is, bound to know
|
|||
|
what is a crime,) is to maintain an entirely arbitrary authority on the
|
|||
|
part of the government, and to deny to the people all right to judge for
|
|||
|
themselves what their own rights and liberties are. In other words, the
|
|||
|
whole object of the doctrine is to deny to the people themselves all
|
|||
|
right to judge what statutes and other acts of the government are
|
|||
|
consistent or inconsistent with their own rights and liberties; and thus
|
|||
|
to reduce the people to the condition of mere slaves to a despotic
|
|||
|
power, such as the people themselves would never have voluntarily
|
|||
|
established, and the justice of whose laws the people themselves cannot
|
|||
|
understand.
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
Under the true trial by jury all tyranny of this kind would be
|
|||
|
abolished. A jury would not only judge what acts were really criminal,
|
|||
|
but they would judge of the mental capacity of an accused person, and of
|
|||
|
his opportunities for understanding the true character of his conduct.
|
|||
|
In short, they would judge of his moral intent from all the
|
|||
|
circumstances of the case, and acquit him, if they had any reasonable
|
|||
|
doubt that he knew that he was committing a crime.[^104]
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
[Footnote 103: This presumption, founded upon age alone, is as absurd in
|
|||
|
civil matters as in criminal. What can be more entirely ludicrous than
|
|||
|
the idea that all men (not manifestly imbecile) become mentally
|
|||
|
competent to make all contracts whatsoever on the day they become
|
|||
|
twenty-one years of age?—and that, previous to that day, no man becomes
|
|||
|
competent to make any contract whatever, except for the present supply
|
|||
|
of the most obvious wants of nature? In reason, a man’s _legal_
|
|||
|
competency to make _binding_ contracts, in any and every case whatever,
|
|||
|
depends wholly upon his _mental_ capacity to make _reasonable_ contracts
|
|||
|
in each particular case. It of course requires more capacity to make a
|
|||
|
reasonable contract in some cases than in others. It requires, for
|
|||
|
example, more capacity to make a reasonable contract in the purchase of
|
|||
|
a large estate, than in the purchase of a pair of shoes. But the mental
|
|||
|
capacity to make a reasonable contract, in any particular case, is, in
|
|||
|
reason, the only legal criterion of the legal competency to make a
|
|||
|
binding contract in that case. The age, whether more or less than
|
|||
|
twenty-one years, is of no legal consequence whatever, except that it is
|
|||
|
entitled to some consideration as _evidence of capacity_.
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
It may be mentioned, in this connection, that the rules that prevail,
|
|||
|
that every man is entitled to freedom from parental authority at
|
|||
|
twenty-one years of age, and no one before that age, are of the same
|
|||
|
class of absurdities with those that have been mentioned. The only
|
|||
|
ground on which a parent is ever entitled to exercise authority over his
|
|||
|
child, is that the child is incapable of taking reasonable care of
|
|||
|
himself. The child would be entitled to his freedom from his birth, if
|
|||
|
he were at that time capable of taking reasonable care of himself. Some
|
|||
|
become capable of taking care of themselves at an earlier age than
|
|||
|
others. And whenever any one becomes capable of taking reasonable care
|
|||
|
of himself, and not until then, he is entitled to his freedom, be his
|
|||
|
age more or less.
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
These principles would prevail under the true trial by jury, the jury
|
|||
|
being the judges of the capacity of every individual whose capacity
|
|||
|
should be called in question.]
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
[Footnote 104: In contrast to the doctrines of the text, it may be
|
|||
|
proper to present more distinctly the doctrines that are maintained by
|
|||
|
judges, and that prevail in courts of justice.
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
Of course, no judge, either of the present day, or perhaps within the
|
|||
|
last five hundred years, has admitted the right of a jury to judge of
|
|||
|
the _justice_ of a law, or to hold any law invalid for its injustice.
|
|||
|
Every judge asserts the power of the government to punish for acts that
|
|||
|
are intrinsically innocent, and which therefore involve or evince no
|
|||
|
criminal intent. To accommodate the administration of law to this
|
|||
|
principle, all judges, so far as I am aware, hold it to be unnecessary
|
|||
|
that an indictment should charge, or that a jury should find, that an
|
|||
|
act was done with a criminal intent, except in those cases where the act
|
|||
|
is _malum in se_,—criminal in itself. In all other cases, so far as I
|
|||
|
am aware, they hold it sufficient that the indictment charge, and
|
|||
|
consequently that the jury find, simply that the act was done “contrary
|
|||
|
to the form of the statute in such case made and provided;” in other
|
|||
|
words, contrary to the orders of the government.
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
All these doctrines prevail universally among judges, and are, I think,
|
|||
|
uniformly practised upon in courts of justice; and they plainly involve
|
|||
|
the most absolute despotism on the part of the government.
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
But there is still another doctrine that extensively, and perhaps most
|
|||
|
generally, prevails in practice, although judges are not agreed in
|
|||
|
regard to its soundness. It is this: that it is not even necessary that
|
|||
|
the jury should see or know, _for themselves_, what the law _is_ that is
|
|||
|
charged to have been violated; nor to see or know, _for themselves_,
|
|||
|
that the act charged was in violation of any law whatever;—but that it
|
|||
|
is sufficient that they be simply _told by the judge_ that any act
|
|||
|
whatever, charged in an indictment, is in violation of law, and that
|
|||
|
they are then bound blindly to receive the declaration as true, and
|
|||
|
convict a man accordingly, if they find that he has done the act
|
|||
|
charged.
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
This doctrine is adopted by many among the most eminent judges, and the
|
|||
|
reasons for it are thus given by Lord Mansfield:
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
> “They (the jury) do not know, and are not presumed to know, the law.
|
|||
|
> They are not sworn to decide the law;[^105] they are not required to
|
|||
|
> do it.... The jury ought not to assume the jurisdiction of law. They
|
|||
|
> do not know, and are not presumed to know, anything of the matter.
|
|||
|
> They do not understand the language in which it is conceived, or the
|
|||
|
> meaning of the terms. They have no rule to go by but their passions
|
|||
|
> and wishes.”—_3 Term Rep._, 428, note.
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
What is this but saying that the people, who are supposed to be
|
|||
|
represented in juries, and who institute and support the government, (of
|
|||
|
course for the protection of their own rights and liberties, _as they
|
|||
|
understand them_, for plainly no other motive can be attributed to
|
|||
|
them,) are really the slaves of a despotic power, whose arbitrary
|
|||
|
commands even they are not supposed competent to understand, but for the
|
|||
|
transgression of which they are nevertheless to be punished as
|
|||
|
criminals?
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
This is plainly the sum of the doctrine, because the jury are the peers
|
|||
|
(equals) of the accused, and are therefore supposed to know the law as
|
|||
|
well as he does, and as well as it is known by the people at large. If
|
|||
|
_they_ (the jury) are not presumed to know the law, neither the accused
|
|||
|
nor the people at large can be presumed to know it. Hence, it follows
|
|||
|
that one principle of the _true_ trial by jury is, that no accused
|
|||
|
person shall be held responsible for any other or greater knowledge of
|
|||
|
the law than is common to his political equals, who will generally be
|
|||
|
men of nearly similar condition in life. But the doctrine of Mansfield
|
|||
|
is, that the body of the people, from whom jurors are taken, are
|
|||
|
responsible to a law, _which it is agreed they cannot understand_. What
|
|||
|
is this but despotism?—and not merely despotism, but insult and
|
|||
|
oppression of the intensest kind?
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
This doctrine of Mansfield is the doctrine of all who deny the right of
|
|||
|
juries to judge of the law, although all may not choose to express it in
|
|||
|
so blunt and unambiguous terms. But the doctrine evidently admits of no
|
|||
|
other interpretation or defence.]
|
|||
|
|
|||
|
[Footnote 105: This declaration of Mansfield, that juries in England
|
|||
|
“are not sworn to decide the law” in criminal cases, is a plain
|
|||
|
falsehood. They are sworn to try the whole case at issue between the
|
|||
|
king and the prisoner, and that includes the law as well as the fact.
|
|||
|
See _juror’s oath_, page 86.]
|