Fix footnote bodies
This commit is contained in:
@ -312,118 +312,118 @@ In short, they would judge of his moral intent from all the
|
||||
circumstances of the case, and acquit him, if they had any reasonable
|
||||
doubt that he knew that he was committing a crime.[^104]
|
||||
|
||||
[Footnote 103: This presumption, founded upon age alone, is as absurd in
|
||||
civil matters as in criminal. What can be more entirely ludicrous than
|
||||
the idea that all men (not manifestly imbecile) become mentally
|
||||
competent to make all contracts whatsoever on the day they become
|
||||
twenty-one years of age?—and that, previous to that day, no man becomes
|
||||
competent to make any contract whatever, except for the present supply
|
||||
of the most obvious wants of nature? In reason, a man’s _legal_
|
||||
competency to make _binding_ contracts, in any and every case whatever,
|
||||
depends wholly upon his _mental_ capacity to make _reasonable_ contracts
|
||||
in each particular case. It of course requires more capacity to make a
|
||||
reasonable contract in some cases than in others. It requires, for
|
||||
example, more capacity to make a reasonable contract in the purchase of
|
||||
a large estate, than in the purchase of a pair of shoes. But the mental
|
||||
capacity to make a reasonable contract, in any particular case, is, in
|
||||
reason, the only legal criterion of the legal competency to make a
|
||||
binding contract in that case. The age, whether more or less than
|
||||
twenty-one years, is of no legal consequence whatever, except that it is
|
||||
entitled to some consideration as _evidence of capacity_.
|
||||
[^103]: This presumption, founded upon age alone, is as absurd in
|
||||
civil matters as in criminal. What can be more entirely ludicrous than
|
||||
the idea that all men (not manifestly imbecile) become mentally
|
||||
competent to make all contracts whatsoever on the day they become
|
||||
twenty-one years of age?—and that, previous to that day, no man becomes
|
||||
competent to make any contract whatever, except for the present supply
|
||||
of the most obvious wants of nature? In reason, a man’s _legal_
|
||||
competency to make _binding_ contracts, in any and every case whatever,
|
||||
depends wholly upon his _mental_ capacity to make _reasonable_ contracts
|
||||
in each particular case. It of course requires more capacity to make a
|
||||
reasonable contract in some cases than in others. It requires, for
|
||||
example, more capacity to make a reasonable contract in the purchase of
|
||||
a large estate, than in the purchase of a pair of shoes. But the mental
|
||||
capacity to make a reasonable contract, in any particular case, is, in
|
||||
reason, the only legal criterion of the legal competency to make a
|
||||
binding contract in that case. The age, whether more or less than
|
||||
twenty-one years, is of no legal consequence whatever, except that it is
|
||||
entitled to some consideration as _evidence of capacity_.
|
||||
|
||||
It may be mentioned, in this connection, that the rules that prevail,
|
||||
that every man is entitled to freedom from parental authority at
|
||||
twenty-one years of age, and no one before that age, are of the same
|
||||
class of absurdities with those that have been mentioned. The only
|
||||
ground on which a parent is ever entitled to exercise authority over his
|
||||
child, is that the child is incapable of taking reasonable care of
|
||||
himself. The child would be entitled to his freedom from his birth, if
|
||||
he were at that time capable of taking reasonable care of himself. Some
|
||||
become capable of taking care of themselves at an earlier age than
|
||||
others. And whenever any one becomes capable of taking reasonable care
|
||||
of himself, and not until then, he is entitled to his freedom, be his
|
||||
age more or less.
|
||||
|
||||
These principles would prevail under the true trial by jury, the jury
|
||||
being the judges of the capacity of every individual whose capacity
|
||||
should be called in question.
|
||||
|
||||
It may be mentioned, in this connection, that the rules that prevail,
|
||||
that every man is entitled to freedom from parental authority at
|
||||
twenty-one years of age, and no one before that age, are of the same
|
||||
class of absurdities with those that have been mentioned. The only
|
||||
ground on which a parent is ever entitled to exercise authority over his
|
||||
child, is that the child is incapable of taking reasonable care of
|
||||
himself. The child would be entitled to his freedom from his birth, if
|
||||
he were at that time capable of taking reasonable care of himself. Some
|
||||
become capable of taking care of themselves at an earlier age than
|
||||
others. And whenever any one becomes capable of taking reasonable care
|
||||
of himself, and not until then, he is entitled to his freedom, be his
|
||||
age more or less.
|
||||
[^104]: In contrast to the doctrines of the text, it may be
|
||||
proper to present more distinctly the doctrines that are maintained by
|
||||
judges, and that prevail in courts of justice.
|
||||
|
||||
Of course, no judge, either of the present day, or perhaps within the
|
||||
last five hundred years, has admitted the right of a jury to judge of
|
||||
the _justice_ of a law, or to hold any law invalid for its injustice.
|
||||
Every judge asserts the power of the government to punish for acts that
|
||||
are intrinsically innocent, and which therefore involve or evince no
|
||||
criminal intent. To accommodate the administration of law to this
|
||||
principle, all judges, so far as I am aware, hold it to be unnecessary
|
||||
that an indictment should charge, or that a jury should find, that an
|
||||
act was done with a criminal intent, except in those cases where the act
|
||||
is _malum in se_,—criminal in itself. In all other cases, so far as I
|
||||
am aware, they hold it sufficient that the indictment charge, and
|
||||
consequently that the jury find, simply that the act was done “contrary
|
||||
to the form of the statute in such case made and provided;” in other
|
||||
words, contrary to the orders of the government.
|
||||
|
||||
All these doctrines prevail universally among judges, and are, I think,
|
||||
uniformly practised upon in courts of justice; and they plainly involve
|
||||
the most absolute despotism on the part of the government.
|
||||
|
||||
But there is still another doctrine that extensively, and perhaps most
|
||||
generally, prevails in practice, although judges are not agreed in
|
||||
regard to its soundness. It is this: that it is not even necessary that
|
||||
the jury should see or know, _for themselves_, what the law _is_ that is
|
||||
charged to have been violated; nor to see or know, _for themselves_,
|
||||
that the act charged was in violation of any law whatever;—but that it
|
||||
is sufficient that they be simply _told by the judge_ that any act
|
||||
whatever, charged in an indictment, is in violation of law, and that
|
||||
they are then bound blindly to receive the declaration as true, and
|
||||
convict a man accordingly, if they find that he has done the act
|
||||
charged.
|
||||
|
||||
This doctrine is adopted by many among the most eminent judges, and the
|
||||
reasons for it are thus given by Lord Mansfield:
|
||||
|
||||
> “They (the jury) do not know, and are not presumed to know, the law.
|
||||
> They are not sworn to decide the law;[^105] they are not required to
|
||||
> do it.... The jury ought not to assume the jurisdiction of law. They
|
||||
> do not know, and are not presumed to know, anything of the matter.
|
||||
> They do not understand the language in which it is conceived, or the
|
||||
> meaning of the terms. They have no rule to go by but their passions
|
||||
> and wishes.”—_3 Term Rep._, 428, note.
|
||||
|
||||
What is this but saying that the people, who are supposed to be
|
||||
represented in juries, and who institute and support the government, (of
|
||||
course for the protection of their own rights and liberties, _as they
|
||||
understand them_, for plainly no other motive can be attributed to
|
||||
them,) are really the slaves of a despotic power, whose arbitrary
|
||||
commands even they are not supposed competent to understand, but for the
|
||||
transgression of which they are nevertheless to be punished as
|
||||
criminals?
|
||||
|
||||
This is plainly the sum of the doctrine, because the jury are the peers
|
||||
(equals) of the accused, and are therefore supposed to know the law as
|
||||
well as he does, and as well as it is known by the people at large. If
|
||||
_they_ (the jury) are not presumed to know the law, neither the accused
|
||||
nor the people at large can be presumed to know it. Hence, it follows
|
||||
that one principle of the _true_ trial by jury is, that no accused
|
||||
person shall be held responsible for any other or greater knowledge of
|
||||
the law than is common to his political equals, who will generally be
|
||||
men of nearly similar condition in life. But the doctrine of Mansfield
|
||||
is, that the body of the people, from whom jurors are taken, are
|
||||
responsible to a law, _which it is agreed they cannot understand_. What
|
||||
is this but despotism?—and not merely despotism, but insult and
|
||||
oppression of the intensest kind?
|
||||
|
||||
This doctrine of Mansfield is the doctrine of all who deny the right of
|
||||
juries to judge of the law, although all may not choose to express it in
|
||||
so blunt and unambiguous terms. But the doctrine evidently admits of no
|
||||
other interpretation or defence.
|
||||
|
||||
These principles would prevail under the true trial by jury, the jury
|
||||
being the judges of the capacity of every individual whose capacity
|
||||
should be called in question.]
|
||||
|
||||
[Footnote 104: In contrast to the doctrines of the text, it may be
|
||||
proper to present more distinctly the doctrines that are maintained by
|
||||
judges, and that prevail in courts of justice.
|
||||
|
||||
Of course, no judge, either of the present day, or perhaps within the
|
||||
last five hundred years, has admitted the right of a jury to judge of
|
||||
the _justice_ of a law, or to hold any law invalid for its injustice.
|
||||
Every judge asserts the power of the government to punish for acts that
|
||||
are intrinsically innocent, and which therefore involve or evince no
|
||||
criminal intent. To accommodate the administration of law to this
|
||||
principle, all judges, so far as I am aware, hold it to be unnecessary
|
||||
that an indictment should charge, or that a jury should find, that an
|
||||
act was done with a criminal intent, except in those cases where the act
|
||||
is _malum in se_,—criminal in itself. In all other cases, so far as I
|
||||
am aware, they hold it sufficient that the indictment charge, and
|
||||
consequently that the jury find, simply that the act was done “contrary
|
||||
to the form of the statute in such case made and provided;” in other
|
||||
words, contrary to the orders of the government.
|
||||
|
||||
All these doctrines prevail universally among judges, and are, I think,
|
||||
uniformly practised upon in courts of justice; and they plainly involve
|
||||
the most absolute despotism on the part of the government.
|
||||
|
||||
But there is still another doctrine that extensively, and perhaps most
|
||||
generally, prevails in practice, although judges are not agreed in
|
||||
regard to its soundness. It is this: that it is not even necessary that
|
||||
the jury should see or know, _for themselves_, what the law _is_ that is
|
||||
charged to have been violated; nor to see or know, _for themselves_,
|
||||
that the act charged was in violation of any law whatever;—but that it
|
||||
is sufficient that they be simply _told by the judge_ that any act
|
||||
whatever, charged in an indictment, is in violation of law, and that
|
||||
they are then bound blindly to receive the declaration as true, and
|
||||
convict a man accordingly, if they find that he has done the act
|
||||
charged.
|
||||
|
||||
This doctrine is adopted by many among the most eminent judges, and the
|
||||
reasons for it are thus given by Lord Mansfield:
|
||||
|
||||
> “They (the jury) do not know, and are not presumed to know, the law.
|
||||
> They are not sworn to decide the law;[^105] they are not required to
|
||||
> do it.... The jury ought not to assume the jurisdiction of law. They
|
||||
> do not know, and are not presumed to know, anything of the matter.
|
||||
> They do not understand the language in which it is conceived, or the
|
||||
> meaning of the terms. They have no rule to go by but their passions
|
||||
> and wishes.”—_3 Term Rep._, 428, note.
|
||||
|
||||
What is this but saying that the people, who are supposed to be
|
||||
represented in juries, and who institute and support the government, (of
|
||||
course for the protection of their own rights and liberties, _as they
|
||||
understand them_, for plainly no other motive can be attributed to
|
||||
them,) are really the slaves of a despotic power, whose arbitrary
|
||||
commands even they are not supposed competent to understand, but for the
|
||||
transgression of which they are nevertheless to be punished as
|
||||
criminals?
|
||||
|
||||
This is plainly the sum of the doctrine, because the jury are the peers
|
||||
(equals) of the accused, and are therefore supposed to know the law as
|
||||
well as he does, and as well as it is known by the people at large. If
|
||||
_they_ (the jury) are not presumed to know the law, neither the accused
|
||||
nor the people at large can be presumed to know it. Hence, it follows
|
||||
that one principle of the _true_ trial by jury is, that no accused
|
||||
person shall be held responsible for any other or greater knowledge of
|
||||
the law than is common to his political equals, who will generally be
|
||||
men of nearly similar condition in life. But the doctrine of Mansfield
|
||||
is, that the body of the people, from whom jurors are taken, are
|
||||
responsible to a law, _which it is agreed they cannot understand_. What
|
||||
is this but despotism?—and not merely despotism, but insult and
|
||||
oppression of the intensest kind?
|
||||
|
||||
This doctrine of Mansfield is the doctrine of all who deny the right of
|
||||
juries to judge of the law, although all may not choose to express it in
|
||||
so blunt and unambiguous terms. But the doctrine evidently admits of no
|
||||
other interpretation or defence.]
|
||||
|
||||
[Footnote 105: This declaration of Mansfield, that juries in England
|
||||
“are not sworn to decide the law” in criminal cases, is a plain
|
||||
falsehood. They are sworn to try the whole case at issue between the
|
||||
king and the prisoner, and that includes the law as well as the fact.
|
||||
See _juror’s oath_, page 86.]
|
||||
[^105]: This declaration of Mansfield, that juries in England
|
||||
“are not sworn to decide the law” in criminal cases, is a plain
|
||||
falsehood. They are sworn to try the whole case at issue between the
|
||||
king and the prisoner, and that includes the law as well as the fact.
|
||||
See _juror’s oath_, page 86.
|
||||
|
Reference in New Issue
Block a user