Fix footnote bodies
This commit is contained in:
@ -469,159 +469,159 @@ An old book, called “English Liberties,” says:
|
||||
> established and confirmed by the legislative power, no one privilege
|
||||
> besides having been ever so often remembered in parliament.”[^114]
|
||||
|
||||
[Footnote 106: _Mackintosh’s Hist. of Eng._, ch. 3. _45 Lardner’s Cab.
|
||||
Cyc._, 354.]
|
||||
[^106]: _Mackintosh’s Hist. of Eng._, ch. 3. _45 Lardner’s Cab.
|
||||
Cyc._, 354.
|
||||
|
||||
[Footnote 107: “_Forty shilling freeholders_” were those “people
|
||||
dwelling and resident in the same counties, whereof every one of them
|
||||
shall have free land or tenement to the value of forty shillings by the
|
||||
year at the least above all charges.” By statute _8 Henry_ 6, ch. 7,
|
||||
(1429,) these freeholders only were allowed to vote for members of
|
||||
Parliament from the _counties_.]
|
||||
[^107]: “_Forty shilling freeholders_” were those “people
|
||||
dwelling and resident in the same counties, whereof every one of them
|
||||
shall have free land or tenement to the value of forty shillings by the
|
||||
year at the least above all charges.” By statute _8 Henry_ 6, ch. 7,
|
||||
(1429,) these freeholders only were allowed to vote for members of
|
||||
Parliament from the _counties_.
|
||||
|
||||
[Footnote 108: He probably speaks in its favor only to blind the eyes of
|
||||
the people to the frauds he has attempted upon its true meaning.]
|
||||
[^108]: He probably speaks in its favor only to blind the eyes of
|
||||
the people to the frauds he has attempted upon its true meaning.
|
||||
|
||||
[Footnote 109: It will be noticed that Coke calls these confirmations of
|
||||
the charter “acts of parliament,” instead of acts of the king alone.
|
||||
This needs explanation.
|
||||
[^109]: It will be noticed that Coke calls these confirmations of
|
||||
the charter “acts of parliament,” instead of acts of the king alone.
|
||||
This needs explanation.
|
||||
|
||||
It was one of Coke’s ridiculous pretences, that laws anciently enacted
|
||||
by the king, at the request, or with the consent, or by the advice, of
|
||||
his parliament, was “an act of parliament,” instead of the act of the
|
||||
king. And in the extracts cited, he carries this idea so far as to
|
||||
pretend that the various confirmations of the Great Charter were “acts
|
||||
of parliament,” instead of the acts of the kings. He might as well have
|
||||
pretended that the original grant of the Charter was an “act of
|
||||
parliament;” because it was not only granted at the request, and with
|
||||
the consent, and by the advice, but on the compulsion even, of those who
|
||||
commonly constituted his parliaments. Yet this did not make the grant of
|
||||
the charter “an act of parliament.” It was simply an act of the king.
|
||||
|
||||
The object of Coke, in this pretence, was to furnish some color for the
|
||||
palpable falsehood that the legislative authority, which parliament was
|
||||
trying to assume in his own day, and which it finally succeeded in
|
||||
obtaining, had a precedent in the ancient constitution of the kingdom.
|
||||
|
||||
There would be as much reason in saying that, because the ancient kings
|
||||
were in the habit of passing laws in special answer to the _petitions_
|
||||
of their subjects, therefore those _petitioners_ were a part of the
|
||||
legislative power of the kingdom.
|
||||
|
||||
One great objection to this argument of Coke, for the legislative
|
||||
authority of the ancient parliaments, is that a very large—probably
|
||||
much the larger—number of legislative acts were done _without_ the
|
||||
advice, consent, request, or even presence, of a parliament. Not only
|
||||
were many formal statutes passed without any mention of the consent or
|
||||
advice of parliament, but a simple order of the king in council, or a
|
||||
simple proclamation, writ, or letter under seal, issued by his command,
|
||||
had the same force as what Coke calls “an act of parliament.” And this
|
||||
practice continued, to a considerable extent at least, down to Coke’s
|
||||
own time.
|
||||
|
||||
The kings were always in the habit of consulting their parliaments, more
|
||||
or less, in regard to matters of legislation,—not because their consent
|
||||
was constitutionally necessary, but in order to make influence in favor
|
||||
of their laws, and thus induce the people to observe them, and the
|
||||
juries to enforce them.
|
||||
|
||||
The general duties of the ancient parliaments were not legislative, but
|
||||
judicial, as will be shown more fully hereafter. The _people_ were not
|
||||
represented in the parliaments at the time of Magna Carta, but only the
|
||||
archbishops, bishops, earls, barons, and knights; so that little or
|
||||
nothing would have been gained for liberty by Coke’s idea that
|
||||
parliament had a legislative power. He would only have substituted an
|
||||
aristocracy for a king. Even after the Commons were represented in
|
||||
parliament, they for some centuries appeared only as _petitioners_,
|
||||
except in the matter of taxation, when their _consent_ was asked. And
|
||||
almost the only source of their influence on legislation was this: that
|
||||
they would sometimes refuse their consent to the taxation, unless the
|
||||
king would pass such laws as they petitioned for; or, as would seem to
|
||||
have been much more frequently the case, unless he would abolish such
|
||||
laws and practices as they remonstrated against.
|
||||
|
||||
The _influence_ or power of parliament, and especially of the Commons,
|
||||
in the general legislation of the country, was a thing of slow growth,
|
||||
having its origin in a device of the king to get money contrary to law,
|
||||
(as will be seen in the next volume,) and not at all a part of the
|
||||
constitution of the kingdom, nor having its foundation in the consent of
|
||||
the people. The power, _as at present exercised_, was not fully
|
||||
established until 1688, (near five hundred years after Magna Carta,)
|
||||
when the House of Commons (falsely so called) had acquired such
|
||||
influence as the representative, _not of the people, but of the wealth,
|
||||
of the nation_, that they compelled the king to discard the oath fixed
|
||||
by the constitution of the kingdom; (which oath has been already given
|
||||
in a former chapter,(page 101) and was, in substance, to preserve and
|
||||
execute the Common Law, the Law of the Land,—or, in the words of the
|
||||
oath, “_the just laws and customs which the common people had chosen_;”)
|
||||
and to swear that he would “govern the people of this kingdom of
|
||||
England, and the dominions thereto belonging, _according to the statutes
|
||||
in parliament agreed on_, and the laws and customs of the same.”[^115]
|
||||
|
||||
The passage and enforcement of this statute, and the assumption of this
|
||||
oath by the king, were plain violations of the English constitution,
|
||||
inasmuch as they abolished, so far as such an oath could abolish, the
|
||||
legislative power of the king, and also “those just laws and customs
|
||||
which the common people (through their juries) had chosen,” and
|
||||
substituted the will of parliament in their stead.
|
||||
|
||||
Coke was a great advocate for the legislative power of parliament, as a
|
||||
means of restraining the power of the king. As he denied all power to
|
||||
_juries_ to decide upon the obligation of laws, and as he held that the
|
||||
legislative power was “_so transcendent and absolute as (that) it cannot
|
||||
be confined, either for causes or persons, within any bounds_,”[^116] he
|
||||
was perhaps honest in holding that it was safer to trust this terrific
|
||||
power in the hands of parliament, than in the hands of the king. His
|
||||
error consisted in holding that either the king or parliament had any
|
||||
such power, or that they had any power at all to pass laws that should
|
||||
be binding upon a jury.
|
||||
|
||||
These declarations of Coke, that the charter was confirmed by thirty-two
|
||||
“acts of parliament,” have a mischievous bearing in another respect.
|
||||
They tend to weaken the authority of the charter, by conveying the
|
||||
impression that the charter itself might be _abolished_ by “act of
|
||||
parliament.” Coke himself admits that it could not be revoked or
|
||||
rescinded by the _king_; for he says, “All pretence of prerogative
|
||||
against Magna Carta is taken away.” (_2 Inst._, 36.)
|
||||
|
||||
He knew perfectly well, and the whole English nation knew, that the
|
||||
_king_ could not lawfully infringe Magna Carta. Magna Carta, therefore,
|
||||
made it impossible that absolute power could ever be practically
|
||||
established in England, _in the hands of the king_. Hence, as Coke was
|
||||
an advocate for absolute power,—that is, for a legislative power “so
|
||||
transcendent and absolute as (that) it cannot be confined, either for
|
||||
causes or persons, within any bounds,”—there was no alternative for him
|
||||
but to vest this absolute power in parliament. Had he not vested it in
|
||||
parliament, he would have been obliged to abjure it altogether, and to
|
||||
confess that the people, _through their juries_, had the right to judge
|
||||
of the obligation of all legislation whatsoever; in other words, that
|
||||
they had the right to confine the government within the limits of “those
|
||||
just laws and customs which the common people (acting as jurors) had
|
||||
chosen.” True to his instincts, as a judge, and as a tyrant, he assumed
|
||||
that this absolute power was vested in the hands of parliament.
|
||||
|
||||
But the truth was that, as by the English constitution parliament had no
|
||||
authority at all for _general_ legislation, it could no more confirm,
|
||||
than it could abolish, Magna Carta.
|
||||
|
||||
These thirty-two confirmations of Magna Carta, which Coke speaks of as
|
||||
“acts of parliament,” were merely acts of the king. The parliaments,
|
||||
indeed, by refusing to grant him money, except on that condition, and
|
||||
otherwise, had contributed to oblige him to make the confirmations; just
|
||||
as they had helped to oblige him by arms to grant the charter in the
|
||||
first place. But the confirmations themselves were nevertheless
|
||||
constitutionally, as well as formally, the acts of the king alone.
|
||||
|
||||
It was one of Coke’s ridiculous pretences, that laws anciently enacted
|
||||
by the king, at the request, or with the consent, or by the advice, of
|
||||
his parliament, was “an act of parliament,” instead of the act of the
|
||||
king. And in the extracts cited, he carries this idea so far as to
|
||||
pretend that the various confirmations of the Great Charter were “acts
|
||||
of parliament,” instead of the acts of the kings. He might as well have
|
||||
pretended that the original grant of the Charter was an “act of
|
||||
parliament;” because it was not only granted at the request, and with
|
||||
the consent, and by the advice, but on the compulsion even, of those who
|
||||
commonly constituted his parliaments. Yet this did not make the grant of
|
||||
the charter “an act of parliament.” It was simply an act of the king.
|
||||
[^110]: Under the head of “_John._”
|
||||
|
||||
The object of Coke, in this pretence, was to furnish some color for the
|
||||
palpable falsehood that the legislative authority, which parliament was
|
||||
trying to assume in his own day, and which it finally succeeded in
|
||||
obtaining, had a precedent in the ancient constitution of the kingdom.
|
||||
[^111]: _4 Blackstone_, 349-50.
|
||||
|
||||
There would be as much reason in saying that, because the ancient kings
|
||||
were in the habit of passing laws in special answer to the _petitions_
|
||||
of their subjects, therefore those _petitioners_ were a part of the
|
||||
legislative power of the kingdom.
|
||||
[^112]: _3 Blackstone_, 379.
|
||||
|
||||
One great objection to this argument of Coke, for the legislative
|
||||
authority of the ancient parliaments, is that a very large—probably
|
||||
much the larger—number of legislative acts were done _without_ the
|
||||
advice, consent, request, or even presence, of a parliament. Not only
|
||||
were many formal statutes passed without any mention of the consent or
|
||||
advice of parliament, but a simple order of the king in council, or a
|
||||
simple proclamation, writ, or letter under seal, issued by his command,
|
||||
had the same force as what Coke calls “an act of parliament.” And this
|
||||
practice continued, to a considerable extent at least, down to Coke’s
|
||||
own time.
|
||||
[^113]: _Hume_, ch. 2.
|
||||
|
||||
The kings were always in the habit of consulting their parliaments, more
|
||||
or less, in regard to matters of legislation,—not because their consent
|
||||
was constitutionally necessary, but in order to make influence in favor
|
||||
of their laws, and thus induce the people to observe them, and the
|
||||
juries to enforce them.
|
||||
[^114]: Page 203, 5th edition, 1721.
|
||||
|
||||
The general duties of the ancient parliaments were not legislative, but
|
||||
judicial, as will be shown more fully hereafter. The _people_ were not
|
||||
represented in the parliaments at the time of Magna Carta, but only the
|
||||
archbishops, bishops, earls, barons, and knights; so that little or
|
||||
nothing would have been gained for liberty by Coke’s idea that
|
||||
parliament had a legislative power. He would only have substituted an
|
||||
aristocracy for a king. Even after the Commons were represented in
|
||||
parliament, they for some centuries appeared only as _petitioners_,
|
||||
except in the matter of taxation, when their _consent_ was asked. And
|
||||
almost the only source of their influence on legislation was this: that
|
||||
they would sometimes refuse their consent to the taxation, unless the
|
||||
king would pass such laws as they petitioned for; or, as would seem to
|
||||
have been much more frequently the case, unless he would abolish such
|
||||
laws and practices as they remonstrated against.
|
||||
[^115]: St. 1 _William and Mary_, ch. 6, (1688.)
|
||||
|
||||
The _influence_ or power of parliament, and especially of the Commons,
|
||||
in the general legislation of the country, was a thing of slow growth,
|
||||
having its origin in a device of the king to get money contrary to law,
|
||||
(as will be seen in the next volume,) and not at all a part of the
|
||||
constitution of the kingdom, nor having its foundation in the consent of
|
||||
the people. The power, _as at present exercised_, was not fully
|
||||
established until 1688, (near five hundred years after Magna Carta,)
|
||||
when the House of Commons (falsely so called) had acquired such
|
||||
influence as the representative, _not of the people, but of the wealth,
|
||||
of the nation_, that they compelled the king to discard the oath fixed
|
||||
by the constitution of the kingdom; (which oath has been already given
|
||||
in a former chapter,(page 101) and was, in substance, to preserve and
|
||||
execute the Common Law, the Law of the Land,—or, in the words of the
|
||||
oath, “_the just laws and customs which the common people had chosen_;”)
|
||||
and to swear that he would “govern the people of this kingdom of
|
||||
England, and the dominions thereto belonging, _according to the statutes
|
||||
in parliament agreed on_, and the laws and customs of the same.”[^115]
|
||||
|
||||
The passage and enforcement of this statute, and the assumption of this
|
||||
oath by the king, were plain violations of the English constitution,
|
||||
inasmuch as they abolished, so far as such an oath could abolish, the
|
||||
legislative power of the king, and also “those just laws and customs
|
||||
which the common people (through their juries) had chosen,” and
|
||||
substituted the will of parliament in their stead.
|
||||
|
||||
Coke was a great advocate for the legislative power of parliament, as a
|
||||
means of restraining the power of the king. As he denied all power to
|
||||
_juries_ to decide upon the obligation of laws, and as he held that the
|
||||
legislative power was “_so transcendent and absolute as (that) it cannot
|
||||
be confined, either for causes or persons, within any bounds_,”[^116] he
|
||||
was perhaps honest in holding that it was safer to trust this terrific
|
||||
power in the hands of parliament, than in the hands of the king. His
|
||||
error consisted in holding that either the king or parliament had any
|
||||
such power, or that they had any power at all to pass laws that should
|
||||
be binding upon a jury.
|
||||
|
||||
These declarations of Coke, that the charter was confirmed by thirty-two
|
||||
“acts of parliament,” have a mischievous bearing in another respect.
|
||||
They tend to weaken the authority of the charter, by conveying the
|
||||
impression that the charter itself might be _abolished_ by “act of
|
||||
parliament.” Coke himself admits that it could not be revoked or
|
||||
rescinded by the _king_; for he says, “All pretence of prerogative
|
||||
against Magna Carta is taken away.” (_2 Inst._, 36.)
|
||||
|
||||
He knew perfectly well, and the whole English nation knew, that the
|
||||
_king_ could not lawfully infringe Magna Carta. Magna Carta, therefore,
|
||||
made it impossible that absolute power could ever be practically
|
||||
established in England, _in the hands of the king_. Hence, as Coke was
|
||||
an advocate for absolute power,—that is, for a legislative power “so
|
||||
transcendent and absolute as (that) it cannot be confined, either for
|
||||
causes or persons, within any bounds,”—there was no alternative for him
|
||||
but to vest this absolute power in parliament. Had he not vested it in
|
||||
parliament, he would have been obliged to abjure it altogether, and to
|
||||
confess that the people, _through their juries_, had the right to judge
|
||||
of the obligation of all legislation whatsoever; in other words, that
|
||||
they had the right to confine the government within the limits of “those
|
||||
just laws and customs which the common people (acting as jurors) had
|
||||
chosen.” True to his instincts, as a judge, and as a tyrant, he assumed
|
||||
that this absolute power was vested in the hands of parliament.
|
||||
|
||||
But the truth was that, as by the English constitution parliament had no
|
||||
authority at all for _general_ legislation, it could no more confirm,
|
||||
than it could abolish, Magna Carta.
|
||||
|
||||
These thirty-two confirmations of Magna Carta, which Coke speaks of as
|
||||
“acts of parliament,” were merely acts of the king. The parliaments,
|
||||
indeed, by refusing to grant him money, except on that condition, and
|
||||
otherwise, had contributed to oblige him to make the confirmations; just
|
||||
as they had helped to oblige him by arms to grant the charter in the
|
||||
first place. But the confirmations themselves were nevertheless
|
||||
constitutionally, as well as formally, the acts of the king alone.]
|
||||
|
||||
[Footnote 110: Under the head of “_John._”]
|
||||
|
||||
[Footnote 111: _4 Blackstone_, 349-50.]
|
||||
|
||||
[Footnote 112: _3 Blackstone_, 379.]
|
||||
|
||||
[Footnote 113: _Hume_, ch. 2.]
|
||||
|
||||
[Footnote 114: Page 203, 5th edition, 1721.]
|
||||
|
||||
[Footnote 115: St. 1 _William and Mary_, ch. 6, (1688.)]
|
||||
|
||||
[Footnote 116: 4 _Inst._, 36.]
|
||||
[^116]: 4 _Inst._, 36.
|
||||
|
Reference in New Issue
Block a user