606 lines
35 KiB
Markdown
606 lines
35 KiB
Markdown
\chapter[Juries Judges of the Justice of Laws.]{The Right of Juries to Judge of the Justice of Laws.}
|
|
\pagestyle{headings}
|
|
|
|
\section[Juries Judges of the Justice of Laws.]{}
|
|
|
|
For more than six hundred years--that is, since Magna Carta, in
|
|
1215--there has been no clearer principle of English or American
|
|
constitutional law, than that, in criminal cases, it is not only the
|
|
right and duty of juries to judge what are the facts, what is the law,
|
|
and what was the moral intent of the accused; _but that it is also their
|
|
right, and their primary and paramount duty, to judge of the justice of
|
|
the law, and to hold all laws invalid, that are, in their opinion,
|
|
unjust or oppressive, and all persons guiltless in violating, or
|
|
resisting the execution of, such laws_.
|
|
|
|
Unless such be the right and duty of jurors, it is plain that, instead
|
|
of juries being a "palladium of liberty"--a barrier against the tyranny
|
|
and oppression of the government--they are really mere tools in its
|
|
hands, for carrying into execution any injustice and oppression it may
|
|
desire to have executed.
|
|
|
|
But for their right to judge of the law, _and the justice of the law_,
|
|
juries would be no protection to an accused person, _even as to matters
|
|
of fact_; for, if the government can dictate to a jury any law whatever,
|
|
in a criminal case, it can certainly dictate to them the laws of
|
|
evidence. That is, it can dictate what evidence is admissible, and what
|
|
inadmissible, _and also what force or weight is to be given to the
|
|
evidence admitted_. And if the government can thus dictate to a jury the
|
|
laws of evidence, it can not only make it necessary for them to convict
|
|
on a partial exhibition of the evidence rightfully pertaining to the
|
|
case, but it can even require them to convict on any evidence whatever
|
|
that it pleases to offer them.
|
|
|
|
That the rights and duties of jurors must necessarily be such as are
|
|
here claimed for them, will be evident when it is considered what the
|
|
trial by jury is, and what is its object.
|
|
|
|
_"The trial by jury," then, is a "trial by the country"--that is, by the
|
|
people--as distinguished from a trial by the government._
|
|
|
|
It was anciently called "trial _per pais_"--that is, "trial by the
|
|
country." And now, in every criminal trial, the jury are told that the
|
|
accused "has, for trial, put himself upon the _country_; which _country_
|
|
you (the jury) are."
|
|
|
|
_The object of this trial "by the country" or by the people, in
|
|
preference to a trial by the government, is to guard against every
|
|
species of oppression by the government. In order to effect this end, it
|
|
is indispensable that the people, or "the country," judge of and
|
|
determine their own liberties against the government; instead of the
|
|
government's judging of and determining its own powers over the people.
|
|
How is it possible that juries can do anything to protect the liberties
|
|
of the people against the government, if they are not allowed to
|
|
determine what those liberties are?_
|
|
|
|
Any government, that is its own judge of, and determines authoritatively
|
|
for the people, what are its own powers over the people, is an absolute
|
|
government of course. It has all the powers that it chooses to exercise.
|
|
There is no other--or at least no more accurate--definition of a
|
|
despotism than this.
|
|
|
|
On the other hand, any people, that judge of, and determine
|
|
authoritatively for the government, what are their own liberties against
|
|
the government, of course retain all the liberties they wish to enjoy.
|
|
_And this is freedom._ At least, it is freedom _to them_; because,
|
|
although it may be theoretically imperfect, it, nevertheless,
|
|
corresponds to _their_ highest notions of freedom.
|
|
|
|
To secure this right of the people to judge of their own liberties
|
|
against the government, the jurors are taken, (or must be, to make them
|
|
lawful jurors,) from the body of the people, _by lot_, or by some
|
|
process that precludes any previous knowledge, choice, or selection of
|
|
them, on the part of the government. This is done to prevent the
|
|
government's constituting a jury of its own partisans or friends; in
|
|
other words, to prevent the government's _packing_ a jury, with a view
|
|
to maintain its own laws, and accomplish its own purposes.
|
|
|
|
It is supposed that, if twelve men be taken, _by lot_, from the mass of
|
|
the people, without the possibility of any previous knowledge, choice,
|
|
or selection of them, on the part of the government, the jury will be a
|
|
fair epitome of "the country" at large, and not merely of the party or
|
|
faction that sustain the measures of the government; that substantially
|
|
all classes of opinions, prevailing among the people, will be
|
|
represented in the jury; and especially that the opponents of the
|
|
government, (if the government have any opponents,) will be represented
|
|
there, as well as its friends; that the classes, who are oppressed by
|
|
the laws of the government, (if any are thus oppressed,) will have their
|
|
representatives in the jury, as well as those classes, who take sides
|
|
with the oppressor--that is, with the government.
|
|
|
|
It is fairly presumable that such a tribunal will agree to no conviction
|
|
except such as _substantially the whole country_ would agree to, if they
|
|
were present, taking part in the trial. A trial by such a tribunal is,
|
|
therefore, in effect, "a trial by the country." In its results it
|
|
probably comes as near to a trial by the _whole_ country, as any trial
|
|
that it is practicable to have, without too great inconvenience and
|
|
expense. And as unanimity is required for a conviction, it follows that
|
|
no one can be convicted, except for the violation of such laws as
|
|
substantially the whole country wish to have maintained. The government
|
|
can enforce none of its laws, (by punishing offenders, through the
|
|
verdicts of juries,) except such as substantially the whole people wish
|
|
to have enforced. The government, therefore, consistently with the trial
|
|
by jury, can exercise no powers over the people, (or, what is the same
|
|
thing, over the accused person, who represents the rights of the
|
|
people,) except such as substantially the whole people of the country
|
|
consent that it may exercise. In such a trial, therefore, "the country,"
|
|
or the people, judge of and determine their own liberties against the
|
|
government, instead of the government's judging of and determining its
|
|
own powers over the people.
|
|
|
|
But all this "trial by the country" would be no trial at all "by the
|
|
country," but only a trial by the government, if the government could
|
|
either declare who may, and who may not, be jurors, or could dictate to
|
|
the jury anything whatever, either of law or evidence, that is of the
|
|
essence of the trial.
|
|
|
|
If the government may decide who may, and who may not, be jurors, it
|
|
will of course select only its partisans, and those friendly to its
|
|
measures. It may not only prescribe who may, and who may not, be
|
|
eligible to be drawn as jurors; but it may also question each person
|
|
drawn as a juror, as to his sentiments in regard to the particular law
|
|
involved in each trial, before suffering him to be sworn on the panel;
|
|
and exclude him if he be found unfavorable to the maintenance of such a
|
|
law.[1]
|
|
|
|
So, also, if the government may dictate to the jury _what laws they are
|
|
to enforce_, it is no longer a "trial by the country," but a trial by
|
|
the government; because the jury then try the accused, not by any
|
|
standard of their own--not by their own judgments of their rightful
|
|
liberties--but by a standard dictated to them by the government. And the
|
|
standard, thus dictated by the government, becomes the measure of the
|
|
people's liberties. If the government dictate the standard of trial, it
|
|
of course dictates the results of the trial. And such a trial is no
|
|
trial by the country, but only a trial by the government; and in it the
|
|
government determines what are its own powers over the people, instead
|
|
of the people's determining what are their own liberties against the
|
|
government. In short, if the jury have no right to judge of the justice
|
|
of a law of the government, they plainly can do nothing to protect the
|
|
people against the oppressions of the government; for there are no
|
|
oppressions which the government may not authorize by law.
|
|
|
|
The jury are also to judge whether the laws are rightly expounded to
|
|
them by the court. Unless they judge on this point, they do nothing to
|
|
protect their liberties against the oppressions that are capable of
|
|
being practised under cover of a corrupt exposition of the laws. If the
|
|
judiciary can authoritatively dictate to a jury any exposition of the
|
|
law, they can dictate to them the law itself, and such laws as they
|
|
please; because laws are, in practice, one thing or another, according
|
|
as they are expounded.
|
|
|
|
The jury must also judge whether there really be any such law, (be it
|
|
good or bad,) as the accused is charged with having transgressed. Unless
|
|
they judge on this point, the people are liable to have their liberties
|
|
taken from them by brute force, without any law at all.
|
|
|
|
The jury must also judge of the laws of evidence. If the government can
|
|
dictate to a jury the laws of evidence, it can not only shut out any
|
|
evidence it pleases, tending to vindicate the accused, but it can
|
|
require that any evidence whatever, that it pleases to offer, be held as
|
|
conclusive proof of any offence whatever which the government chooses to
|
|
allege.
|
|
|
|
It is manifest, therefore, that the jury must judge of and try the whole
|
|
case, and every part and parcel of the case, free of any dictation or
|
|
authority on the part of the government. They must judge of the
|
|
existence of the law; of the true exposition of the law; _of the justice
|
|
of the law_; and of the admissibility and weight of all the evidence
|
|
offered; otherwise the government will have everything its own way; the
|
|
jury will be mere puppets in the hands of the government; and the trial
|
|
will be, in reality, a trial by the government, and not a "trial by the
|
|
country." By such trials the government will determine its own powers
|
|
over the people, instead of the people's determining their own liberties
|
|
against the government; and it will be an entire delusion to talk, as
|
|
for centuries we have done, of the trial by jury, as a "palladium of
|
|
liberty," or as any protection to the people against the oppression and
|
|
tyranny of the government.
|
|
|
|
The question, then, between trial by jury, as thus described, and trial
|
|
by the government, is simply a question between liberty and despotism.
|
|
The authority to judge what are the powers of the government, and what
|
|
the liberties of the people, must necessarily be vested in one or the
|
|
other of the parties themselves--the government, or the people; because
|
|
there is no third party to whom it can be entrusted. If the authority be
|
|
vested in the government, the government is absolute, and the people
|
|
have no liberties except such as the government sees fit to indulge them
|
|
with. If, on the other hand, that authority be vested in the people,
|
|
then the people have all liberties, (as against the government,) except
|
|
such as substantially the whole people (through a jury) choose to
|
|
disclaim; and the government can exercise no power except such as
|
|
substantially the whole people (through a jury) consent that it may
|
|
exercise.
|
|
|
|
|
|
\section[Juries Judges of the Justice of Laws.]{}
|
|
|
|
The force and justice of the preceding argument cannot be evaded by
|
|
saying that the government is chosen by the people; that, in theory, it
|
|
represents the people; that it is designed to do the will of the people;
|
|
that its members are all sworn to observe the fundamental or
|
|
constitutional law instituted by the people; that its acts are therefore
|
|
entitled to be considered the acts of the people; and that to allow a
|
|
jury, representing the people, to invalidate the acts of the government,
|
|
would therefore be arraying the people against themselves.
|
|
|
|
There are two answers to such an argument.
|
|
|
|
One answer is, that, in a representative government, there is no
|
|
absurdity or contradiction, nor any arraying of the people against
|
|
themselves, in requiring that the statutes or enactments of the
|
|
government shall pass the ordeal of any number of separate tribunals,
|
|
before it shall be determined that they are to have the force of laws.
|
|
Our American constitutions have provided five of these separate
|
|
tribunals, to wit, representatives, senate, executive,[2] jury, and
|
|
judges; and have made it necessary that each enactment shall pass the
|
|
ordeal of all these separate tribunals, before its authority can be
|
|
established by the punishment of those who choose to transgress it. And
|
|
there is no more absurdity or inconsistency in making a jury one of
|
|
these several tribunals, than there is in making the representatives, or
|
|
the senate, or the executive, or the judges, one of them. There is no
|
|
more absurdity in giving a jury a veto upon the laws, than there is in
|
|
giving a veto to each of these other tribunals. The people are no more
|
|
arrayed against themselves, when a jury puts its veto upon a statute,
|
|
which the other tribunals have sanctioned, than they are when the same
|
|
veto is exercised by the representatives, the senate, the executive, or
|
|
the judges.
|
|
|
|
But another answer to the argument that the people are arrayed against
|
|
themselves, when a jury hold an enactment of the government invalid, is,
|
|
that the government, and all the departments of the government, _are
|
|
merely the servants and agents of the people_; not invested with
|
|
arbitrary or absolute authority to bind the people, but required to
|
|
submit all their enactments to the judgment of a tribunal more fairly
|
|
representing the whole people, before they carry them into execution, by
|
|
punishing any individual for transgressing them. If the government were
|
|
not thus required to submit their enactments to the judgment of "the
|
|
country," before executing them upon individuals--if, in other words,
|
|
the people had reserved to themselves no veto upon the acts of the
|
|
government, the government, instead of being a mere servant and agent of
|
|
the people, would be an absolute despot over the people. It would have
|
|
all power in its own hands; because the power to _punish_ carries all
|
|
other powers with it. A power that can, of itself, and by its own
|
|
authority, punish disobedience, can compel obedience and submission, and
|
|
is above all responsibility for the character of its laws. In short, it
|
|
is a despotism.
|
|
|
|
And it is of no consequence to inquire how a government came by this
|
|
power to punish, whether by prescription, by inheritance, by usurpation,
|
|
or by delegation from the people? _If it have now but got it_, the
|
|
government is absolute.
|
|
|
|
It is plain, therefore, that if the people have invested the government
|
|
with power to make laws that absolutely bind the people, and to punish
|
|
the people for transgressing those laws, the people have surrendered
|
|
their liberties unreservedly into the hands of the government.
|
|
|
|
It is of no avail to say, in answer to this view of the case, that in
|
|
surrendering their liberties into the hands of the government, the
|
|
people took an oath from the government, that it would exercise its
|
|
power within certain constitutional limits; for when did oaths ever
|
|
restrain a government that was otherwise unrestrained? Or when did a
|
|
government fail to determine that all its acts were within the
|
|
constitutional and authorized limits of its power, if it were permitted
|
|
to determine that question for itself?
|
|
|
|
Neither is it of any avail to say, that, if the government abuse its
|
|
power, and enact unjust and oppressive laws, the government may be
|
|
changed by the influence of discussion, and the exercise of the right of
|
|
suffrage. Discussion can do nothing to prevent the enactment, or procure
|
|
the repeal, of unjust laws, unless it be understood that the discussion
|
|
is to be followed by resistance. Tyrants care nothing for discussions
|
|
that are to end only in discussion. Discussions, which do not interfere
|
|
with the enforcement of their laws, are but idle wind to them. Suffrage
|
|
is equally powerless and unreliable. It can be exercised only
|
|
periodically; and the tyranny must at least be borne until the time for
|
|
suffrage comes. Besides, when the suffrage is exercised, it gives no
|
|
guaranty for the repeal of existing laws that are oppressive, and no
|
|
security against the enactment of new ones that are equally so. The
|
|
second body of legislators are liable and likely to be just as
|
|
tyrannical as the first. If it be said that the second body may be
|
|
chosen for their integrity, the answer is, that the first were chosen
|
|
for that very reason, and yet proved tyrants. The second will be exposed
|
|
to the same temptations as the first, and will be just as likely to
|
|
prove tyrannical. Who ever heard that succeeding legislatures were, on
|
|
the whole, more honest than those that preceded them? What is there in
|
|
the nature of men or things to make them so? If it be said that the first
|
|
body were chosen from motives of injustice, that fact proves that there is
|
|
a portion of society who desire to establish injustice; and if they were
|
|
powerful or artful enough to procure the election of their instruments to
|
|
compose the first legislature, they will be likely to be powerful or
|
|
artful enough to procure the election of the same or similar instruments
|
|
to compose the second. The right of suffrage, therefore, and even a change
|
|
of legislators, guarantees no change of legislation--certainly no change
|
|
for the better. Even if a change for the better actually comes, it comes
|
|
too late, because it comes only after more or less injustice has been
|
|
irreparably done.
|
|
|
|
But, at best, the right of suffrage can be exercised only periodically;
|
|
and between the periods the legislators are wholly irresponsible. No
|
|
despot was ever more entirely irresponsible than are republican
|
|
legislators during the period for which they are chosen. They can
|
|
neither be removed from their office, nor called to account while in
|
|
their office, nor punished after they leave their office, be their
|
|
tyranny what it may. Moreover, the judicial and executive departments of
|
|
the government are equally irresponsible _to the people_, and are only
|
|
responsible, (by impeachment, and dependence for their salaries), to
|
|
these irresponsible legislators. This dependence of the judiciary and
|
|
executive upon the legislature is a guaranty that they will always
|
|
sanction and execute its laws, whether just or unjust. Thus the
|
|
legislators hold the whole power of the government in their hands, and
|
|
are at the same time utterly irresponsible for the manner in which they
|
|
use it.
|
|
|
|
If, now, this government, (the three branches thus really united in
|
|
one), can determine the validity of, and enforce, its own laws, it is,
|
|
for the time being, entirely absolute, and wholly irresponsible to the
|
|
people.
|
|
|
|
But this is not all. These legislators, and this government, so
|
|
irresponsible while in power, can perpetuate their power at pleasure, if
|
|
they can determine what legislation is authoritative upon the people,
|
|
and can enforce obedience to it; for they can not only declare their
|
|
power perpetual, but they can enforce submission to all legislation that
|
|
is necessary to secure its perpetuity. They can, for example, prohibit
|
|
all discussion of the rightfulness of their authority; forbid the use of
|
|
the suffrage; prevent the election of any successors; disarm, plunder,
|
|
imprison, and even kill all who refuse submission. If, therefore, the
|
|
government (all departments united) be absolute for a day--that is, if
|
|
it can, for a day, enforce obedience to its own laws--it can, in that
|
|
day, secure its power for all time--like the queen, who wished to reign
|
|
but for a day, but in that day caused the king, her husband, to be
|
|
slain, and usurped his throne.
|
|
|
|
Nor will it avail to say that such acts would be unconstitutional, and
|
|
that unconstitutional acts may be lawfully resisted; for everything a
|
|
government pleases to do will, of course, be determined to be
|
|
constitutional, if the government itself be permitted to determine the
|
|
question of the constitutionality of its own acts. Those who are capable
|
|
of tyranny, are capable of perjury to sustain it.
|
|
|
|
The conclusion, therefore, is, that any government, that can, _for a
|
|
day_, enforce its own laws, without appealing to the people, (or to a
|
|
tribunal fairly representing the people,) for their consent, is, in
|
|
theory, an absolute government, irresponsible to the people, and can
|
|
perpetuate its power at pleasure.
|
|
|
|
The trial by jury is based upon a recognition of this principle, and
|
|
therefore forbids the government to execute any of its laws, by
|
|
punishing violators, in any case whatever, without first getting the
|
|
consent of "the country," or the people, through a jury. In this way,
|
|
the people, at all times, hold their liberties in their own hands, and
|
|
never surrender them, even for a moment, into the hands of the
|
|
government.
|
|
|
|
The trial by jury, then, gives to any and every individual the liberty,
|
|
at any time, to disregard or resist any law whatever of the government,
|
|
if he be willing to submit to the decision of a jury, the questions,
|
|
whether the law be intrinsically just and obligatory? and whether his
|
|
conduct, in disregarding or resisting it, were right in itself? And any
|
|
law, which does not, in such trial, obtain the unanimous sanction of
|
|
twelve men, taken at random from the people, and judging according to
|
|
the standard of justice in their own minds, free from all dictation and
|
|
authority of the government, may be transgressed and resisted with
|
|
impunity, by whomsoever pleases to transgress or resist it.[3]
|
|
|
|
The trial by jury authorizes all this, or it is a sham and a hoax,
|
|
utterly worthless for protecting the people against oppression. If it do
|
|
not authorize an individual to resist the first and least act of
|
|
injustice or tyranny, on the part of the government, it does not
|
|
authorize him to resist the last and the greatest. If it do not
|
|
authorize individuals to nip tyranny in the bud, it does not authorize
|
|
them to cut it down when its branches are filled with the ripe fruits of
|
|
plunder and oppression.
|
|
|
|
Those who deny the right of a jury to protect an individual in resisting
|
|
an unjust law of the government, deny him all _legal_ defence
|
|
whatsoever against oppression. The right of revolution, which tyrants,
|
|
in mockery, accord to mankind, is no _legal_ right _under_ a government;
|
|
it is only a _natural_ right to overturn a government. The government
|
|
itself never acknowledges this right. And the right is practically
|
|
established only when and because the government no longer exists to
|
|
call it in question. The right, therefore, can be exercised with
|
|
impunity, only when it is exercised victoriously. All _unsuccessful_
|
|
attempts at revolution, however justifiable in themselves, are punished
|
|
as treason, if the government be permitted to judge of the treason. The
|
|
government itself never admits the injustice of its laws, as a legal
|
|
defence for those who have attempted a revolution, and failed. The right
|
|
of revolution, therefore, is a right of no practical value, except for
|
|
those who are stronger than the government. So long, therefore, as the
|
|
oppressions of a government are kept within such limits as simply not to
|
|
exasperate against it a power greater than its own, the right of
|
|
revolution cannot be appealed to, and is therefore inapplicable to the
|
|
case. This affords a wide field for tyranny; and if a jury cannot _here_
|
|
intervene, the oppressed are utterly defenceless.
|
|
|
|
It is manifest that the only security against the tyranny of the
|
|
government lies in forcible resistance to the execution of the
|
|
injustice; because the injustice will certainly be executed, _unless it
|
|
be forcibly resisted_. And if it be but suffered to be executed, it must
|
|
then be borne; for the government never makes compensation for its own
|
|
wrongs.
|
|
|
|
Since, then, this forcible resistance to the injustice of the government
|
|
is the only possible means of preserving liberty, it is indispensable to
|
|
all _legal_ liberty that this _resistance_ should be _legalized_. It is
|
|
perfectly self-evident that where there is no _legal_ right to resist
|
|
the oppression of the government, there can be no _legal_ liberty. And
|
|
here it is all-important to notice, that, _practically speaking_, there
|
|
can be no _legal_ right to resist the oppressions of the government,
|
|
unless there be some _legal_ tribunal, other than the government, and
|
|
wholly independent of, and _above_, the government, to judge between the
|
|
government and those who resist its oppressions; in other words, to
|
|
judge what laws of the government are to be obeyed, and what may be
|
|
resisted and held for nought. The only tribunal known to our laws, for
|
|
this purpose, is a jury. If a jury have not the right to judge between
|
|
the government and those who disobey its laws, and resist its
|
|
oppressions, the government is absolute, and the people, _legally
|
|
speaking_, are slaves. Like many other slaves they may have sufficient
|
|
courage and strength to keep their masters somewhat in check; but they
|
|
are nevertheless _known to the law_ only as slaves.
|
|
|
|
That this right of resistance was recognized as a common law right, when
|
|
the ancient and genuine trial by jury was in force, is not only proved
|
|
by the nature of the trial itself, but is acknowledged by history.[4]
|
|
|
|
This right of resistance is recognized by the constitution of the United
|
|
States, as a strictly legal and constitutional right. It is so
|
|
recognized, first by the provision that "the trial of all crimes, except
|
|
in cases of impeachment, shall be by jury"--that is, by the country--and
|
|
not by the government; secondly, by the provision that "the right of the
|
|
people to keep and bear arms shall not be infringed." This
|
|
constitutional security for "the right to keep and bear arms," implies
|
|
the right to use them--as much as a constitutional security for the
|
|
right to buy and keep food would have implied the right to eat it. The
|
|
constitution, therefore, takes it for granted that the people will
|
|
judge of the conduct of the government, and that, as they have the
|
|
right, they will also have the sense, to use arms, whenever the
|
|
necessity of the case justifies it. And it is a sufficient and _legal_
|
|
defence for a person accused of using arms against the government, if he
|
|
can show, to the satisfaction of a jury, _or even any one of a jury_,
|
|
that the law he resisted was an unjust one.
|
|
|
|
In the American _State_ constitutions also, this right of resistance to
|
|
the oppressions of the government is recognized, in various ways, as a
|
|
natural, legal, and constitutional right. In the first place, it is so
|
|
recognized by provisions establishing the trial by jury; thus requiring
|
|
that accused persons shall be tried by "the country," instead of the
|
|
government. In the second place, it is recognized by many of them, as,
|
|
for example, those of Massachusetts, Maine, Vermont, Connecticut,
|
|
Pennsylvania, Ohio, Indiana, Michigan, Kentucky, Tennessee, Arkansas,
|
|
Mississippi, Alabama, and Florida, by provisions expressly declaring
|
|
that the people shall have the right to bear arms. In many of them also,
|
|
as, for example, those of Maine, New Hampshire, Vermont, Massachusetts,
|
|
New Jersey, Pennsylvania, Delaware, Ohio, Indiana, Illinois, Florida,
|
|
Iowa, and Arkansas, by provisions, in their bills of rights, declaring
|
|
that men have a natural, inherent, and inalienable right of "_defending_
|
|
their lives and liberties." This, of course, means that they have a
|
|
right to defend them against any injustice _on the part of the
|
|
government_, and not merely on the part of private individuals; because
|
|
the object of all bills of rights is to assert the rights of individuals
|
|
and the people, _as against the government_, and not as against private
|
|
persons. It would be a matter of ridiculous supererogation to assert, in
|
|
a constitution of government, the natural right of men to defend their
|
|
lives and liberties against private trespassers.
|
|
|
|
Many of these bills of rights also assert the natural right of all men
|
|
to protect their property--that is, to protect it _against the
|
|
government_. It would be unnecessary and silly indeed to assert, in a
|
|
constitution of government, the natural right of individuals to protect
|
|
their property against thieves and robbers.
|
|
|
|
The constitutions of New Hampshire and Tennessee also declare that "The
|
|
doctrine of non-resistance against arbitrary power and oppression is
|
|
absurd, slavish, and destructive of the good and happiness of mankind."
|
|
|
|
The legal effect of these constitutional recognitions of the right of
|
|
individuals to defend their property, liberties, and lives, against the
|
|
government, is to legalize resistance to all injustice and oppression,
|
|
of every name and nature whatsoever, on the part of the government.
|
|
|
|
But for this right of resistance, on the part of the people, all
|
|
governments would become tyrannical to a degree of which few people are
|
|
aware. Constitutions are utterly worthless to restrain the tyranny of
|
|
governments, unless it be understood that the people will, by force,
|
|
compel the government to keep within the constitutional limits.
|
|
Practically speaking, no government knows any limits to its power,
|
|
except the endurance of the people. But that the people are stronger
|
|
than the government, and will resist in extreme cases, our governments
|
|
would be little or nothing else than organized systems of plunder and
|
|
oppression. All, or nearly all, the advantage there is in fixing any
|
|
constitutional limits to the power of a government, is simply to give
|
|
notice to the government of the point at which it will meet with
|
|
resistance. If the people are then as good as their word, they may keep
|
|
the government within the bounds they have set for it; otherwise it will
|
|
disregard them--as is proved by the example of all our American
|
|
governments, in which the constitutions have all become obsolete, at the
|
|
moment of their adoption, for nearly or quite all purposes except the
|
|
appointment of officers, who at once become practically absolute, except
|
|
so far as they are restrained by the fear of popular resistance.
|
|
|
|
The bounds set to the power of the government, by the trial by jury, as
|
|
will hereafter be shown, are these--that the government shall never
|
|
touch the property, person, or natural or civil rights of an individual,
|
|
against his consent, (except for the purpose of bringing them before a
|
|
jury for trial,) unless in pursuance and _execution_ of a judgment, or
|
|
decree, rendered by a jury in each individual case, upon such evidence,
|
|
and such law, as are satisfactory to their own understandings and
|
|
consciences, irrespective of all legislation of the government.
|
|
|
|
[Footnote 1: To show that this supposition is not an extravagant one, it
|
|
may be mentioned that courts have repeatedly questioned jurors to
|
|
ascertain whether they were prejudiced _against the government_--that
|
|
is, whether they were in favor of, or opposed to, such laws of the
|
|
government as were to be put in issue in the then pending trial. This
|
|
was done (in 1851) in the United States District Court for the District
|
|
of Massachusetts, by Peleg Sprague, the United States district judge, in
|
|
empanelling three several juries for the trials of Scott, Hayden, and
|
|
Morris, charged with having aided in the rescue of a fugitive slave from
|
|
the custody of the United States deputy marshal. This judge caused the
|
|
following question to be propounded to all the jurors separately; and
|
|
those who answered unfavorably for the purposes of the government, were
|
|
excluded from the panel.
|
|
|
|
"Do you hold any opinions upon the subject of the Fugitive Slave Law,
|
|
so called, which will induce you to refuse to convict a person
|
|
indicted under it, if the facts set forth in the indictment, _and
|
|
constituting the offence_, are proved against him, and the court
|
|
direct you that the law is constitutional?"
|
|
|
|
The reason of this question was, that "the Fugitive Slave Law, so
|
|
called," was so obnoxious to a large portion of the people, as to render
|
|
a conviction under it hopeless, if the jurors were taken
|
|
indiscriminately from among the people.
|
|
|
|
A similar question was soon afterwards propounded to the persons drawn
|
|
as jurors in the United States _Circuit_ Court for the District of
|
|
Massachusetts, by Benjamin R. Curtis one of the Justices of the Supreme
|
|
Court of the United States, in empanelling a jury for the trial of the
|
|
aforesaid Morris on the charge before mentioned; and those who did not
|
|
answer the question favorably for the government were again excluded
|
|
from the panel.
|
|
|
|
It has also been an habitual practice with the Supreme Court of
|
|
Massachusetts, in empanelling juries for the trial of _capital_
|
|
offences, to inquire of the persons drawn as jurors whether they had any
|
|
conscientious scruples against finding verdicts of guilty in such cases;
|
|
that is, whether they had any conscientious scruples against sustaining
|
|
the law prescribing death as the punishment of the crime to be tried;
|
|
and to exclude from the panel all who answered in the affirmative.
|
|
|
|
The only principle upon which these questions are asked, is this--that
|
|
no man shall be allowed to serve as juror, unless he be ready to enforce
|
|
any enactment of the government, however cruel or tyrannical it may be.
|
|
|
|
What is such a jury good for, as a protection against the tyranny of the
|
|
government? A jury like that is palpably nothing but a mere tool of
|
|
oppression in the hands of the government. A trial by such a jury is
|
|
really a trial by the government itself--and not a trial by the
|
|
country--because it is a trial only by men specially selected by the
|
|
government for their readiness to enforce its own tyrannical measures.
|
|
|
|
If that be the true principle of the trial by jury, the trial is utterly
|
|
worthless as a security to liberty. The Czar might, with perfect safety
|
|
to his authority, introduce the trial by jury into Russia, if he could
|
|
but be permitted to select his jurors from those who were ready to
|
|
maintain his laws, without regard to their injustice.
|
|
|
|
This example is sufficient to show that the very pith of the trial by
|
|
jury, as a safeguard to liberty, consists in the jurors being taken
|
|
indiscriminately from the whole people, and in their right to hold
|
|
invalid all laws which they think unjust.]
|
|
|
|
[Footnote 2: The executive has a qualified veto upon the passage of
|
|
laws, in most of our governments, and an absolute veto, in all of them,
|
|
upon the execution of any laws which he deems unconstitutional; because
|
|
his oath to support the constitution (as he understands it) forbids him
|
|
to execute any law that he deems unconstitutional.]
|
|
|
|
[Footnote 3: And if there be so much as a reasonable _doubt_ of the
|
|
justice of the laws, the benefit of that doubt must be given to the
|
|
defendant, and not to the government. So that the government must keep
|
|
its laws _clearly_ within the limits of justice, if it would ask a jury
|
|
to enforce them.]
|
|
|
|
[Footnote 4: _Hallam_ says, "The relation established between a lord and
|
|
his vassal by the feudal tenure, far from containing principles of any
|
|
servile and implicit obedience, permitted the compact to be dissolved in
|
|
case of its violation by either party. This extended as much to the
|
|
sovereign as to inferior lords. * * If a vassal was aggrieved, and if
|
|
justice was denied him, he sent a defiance, that is, a renunciation of
|
|
fealty to the king, and was entitled to enforce redress at the point of
|
|
his sword. It then became a contest of strength as between two
|
|
independent potentates, and was terminated by treaty, advantageous or
|
|
otherwise, according to the fortune of war. * * There remained the
|
|
original principle, that allegiance depended conditionally upon good
|
|
treatment, and that an appeal might be _lawfully_ made to arms against
|
|
an oppressive government. Nor was this, we may be sure, left for extreme
|
|
necessity, or thought to require a long-enduring forbearance. In modern
|
|
times, a king, compelled by his subjects' swords to abandon any
|
|
pretension, would be supposed to have ceased to reign; and the express
|
|
recognition of such a right as that of insurrection has been justly
|
|
deemed inconsistent with the majesty of law. But ruder ages had ruder
|
|
sentiments. Force was necessary to repel force; and men accustomed to
|
|
see the king's authority defied by a private riot, were not much shocked
|
|
when it was resisted in defence of public freedom."--_3 Middle Ages_,
|
|
240-2.]
|